1. Introduction
The Intermediate Value Theorem (for short, TVI) is a popular concept in real analysis that freshmen learn in their College first calculus course. For recall that if
is continuous (
), then
; thus all values between
and
are reached by
. So, in order to elaborate on this, we start with the following definitions.
Definition 1.1 Let
and
be two partially ordered sets. We say that
embeds in
whenever there is an injective function
↪
so that:
implies
.
Definition 1.2 A chain
is called an order-scattered chain whenever
does not embed in
.
Next, the following examples, from general literature, shed light on what topological property should
, the set of discontinuities of
, have to ensure TVI-property for
. This is stated in the main theorem of this note.
Example 1.3
There is a function
so that
is uncountable and the interior of
is empty:
For, consider Dirichlet’s function (rational indicator function):
, if
is rational and 0, otherwise.
This is discontinuous everywhere.
Example 1.4
There is a function
so that
is a countable dense set; moreover, the interior of
is empty:
For, consider Thomae’s function, see [1]:
, if
and
for
,
co-prime i.e., their greatest common divisor is 1,
, otherwise.
This is continuous only at the irrational numbers.
Example 1.5
There is a function
so that
is an uncountable set:
For, consider Cantor indicator function:
, if
is in the Cantor set,
, otherwise.
This is continuous only at numbers not in the Cantor set.
This note is organized as follows:
In Section 2, we supply a concrete representation of elements of Int, the class of Boolean algebras over linearly ordered sets (Theorem 2.3); in addiction, Theorems 2.5 and 2.6 are proved. Next, scatterdness, in ordinal/topological sense, for linearly ordered sets, (Lemma 2.4 and Theorem 2.5), is established. In section 3, we state the main theorem (Theorem 2.8).
Recall that a Hausdorff space
(for short,
-space) is a topological space
in which two different points
are separated by two disjoint open sets in
(that is to say, there are two disjoint open sets
and
in
so that
and
). Next, let
(respectively
) be the set of rational numbers with its usual linear ordering (respectively
be the set of real numbers with its usual linear ordering
and endowed with the interval topology). Finally, denote by
the set of discontinuities of any function
.
A linear ordering
is a partially ordering in which two different elements are comparable with respect to
(linear ordering is used interchangeably with a chain). Now, if
is a chain, set
and consider the subalgebra, of the power set Boolean algebra
, generated by
; it is called the interval algebra over the chain
and denoted by
. Whenever,
has a least element, the Stone space associated with
,
, is homeomorphic to
, the set of initial chains in
, that is to say, sets that are either empty or closed downwards in
, endowed with Tychonoff’s topology inherited from
. Indeed,
defined by
is a homeomorphism, see [2].
2. Scattered Chains in
versus Countable Ordinals
Recall the Cantor-Bendixon’s derivation of a topological space. For, let
be a Hausdorff topological space and
is a non empty subset of
. We say that
is an isolated point in
, whenever there is an open set,
containing
, of
so that
. The set of isolated points of
is denoted by
. Hence, for
a Hausdorff space, by induction on the ordinal
, define the
-Cantor derivative of
, as follows:
(2.1)
(2.2)
(2.3)
(2.4)
Thus,
is a decreasing sequence of closed subsets of
, which is actually a stationary sequence i.e., there is a first ordinal
, called the rank of
and denoted by
so that
. Thus, either
, or
.
Definition 2.1 A Hausdorff space
is called topologically scattered space whenever every closed subspace has an isolated point.
Proposition 2.2 For any non empty Hausdorff compact and topologically scattered space
, the first
so that
is a successor ordinal i.e.,
and thus
is a finite set.
Indeed, if
is a limit ordinal and if
, then, by compactness
, for some
: Contradiction.
Next, recall that a Boolean algebra
is called scattered whenever its Stone space,
, is a scattered topological space; sometime we use interchangeably the word superatomic Boolean algebras for scattered Boolean algebras. Moreover, if
denotes
, then
. Thus, it follows that, whenever
is a scattered topological space,
, see [3], [Vol.1, Theorem.15.7., pp. 274].
In this section we give a characterization of countable topologically scattered compact spaces. We start with the following result.
Theorem 2.3
1) Any countable Boolean algebra
is generated by a chain.
2) Let
be a Boolean algebra generated by a chain
in
. Then there is a chain
with a least element so that
is isomorphic to
. Moreover, the Stone space of
, denoted by
, is homeomorphic to the set of initial chains
, endowed with Tychonoff’s Topology inherited from
.
The first part of this theorem appeared in [4]; here, we supply a proof. So, enumerate the whole algebra and construct, by induction, the ad hoc chain. Indeed, for let
be a countable enumeration of
. Denote by
the complement of any
in
; then construct, by induction, a chain
, so that
.
Step 0. Let
. Set
and
.
Step 1. If
, we set
and
If
, we set
Notice that
is a chain, then put
,
and
. Now, to check that
is in
, notice that
Step
Suppose that chains
are constructed so that:
, and
.
Now to finish up the
step, assume that
and look at
.
Case 1.
. In this case we put
.
Case 2.
. In this case, define a new sequence
by
for
.
Note that
Set
Next for each
,
and, by induction,
Hence,
This finishes the induction step. Thus,
. which shows that
is generated by the chain
.
2) Let
where
is the inclusion between subsets of
,
and define
by
. Here, use Sikorski’s extension criterion to extend
to a homomorphism
. Then
is onto since
is by construction. By, Sikorski’s extension criterion again, the one-to-oness follows.
3) The function
, defined by,
, is a homeomorphism from
onto the set of initial chains
.
Lemma 2.4 Let
be a complete chain. If
is a scattered topological space, then
does not embed into
as an order set. Notice that the assumption of completeness of
is necessary.
1) First, recall that
denotes the topological closure of
in
, where
, is endowed with the interval topology. Second, if
is infinite, then . This follows since
is a compact. Now suppose that
is a chain order isomorphic the
: We shall get a contradiction. Choose ,
isolated in
. Say,
;
.
2) There are
,
so that
, and
. In fact, since , the set
is infinite. Hence there clearly exist
such that
and
. Choose
,
; this proves 2). Now, taking
and
as in 2), put
. So
has type
. Clearly . Picking
in by 1), we obtain
, contradiction.
3) To see the necessity of completeness, let
, where
with its natural ordering. Now, for
, set:
if, and only if
either (
,
, and
) or (
, for some
and
).
It follows that
is a chain that is a counterexample.
Theorem 2.5
Let
be a chain with a least element and
be the inclusion of sets. Then, the following are equivalent:
1)
does not embed into
;
2)
does not embed into
is considered as an order set;
3)
does not embed into
is considered as a topological space;
4)
does not embed into
i.e.,
is a superatomic interval algebra.
3) and 4) are equivalent by the duality theory. 2) implies 1) since
embeds in
. 1) implies 4) since a quotient of
is isomorphic to
for some subchain
of
(see Theorem 15.22, p. 253 in [2]). Finally, 3) implies 2) by Lemma 2.4.
Next theorem characterizes countable topological scattered compact spaces.
Theorem 2.6 Let
be a Hausdorff topologically scattered compact space. Then the following are equivalent statements.
1) Each point of
has a countable basis,
2)
is homeomorphic to a countable ordinal,
3)
is a countable set.
2) implies 2) and 3) implies 2) are trivial. We only prove 1) implies 2) by induction on
. For assume that
is a finite set, for some ordinal
. Hence, we may assume that the kernel of
, denoted by
. Now, pick a countable strictly decreasing sequence,
of clopen sets of
so that
. Set
. It follows that
, so that
is a clopen subset of
of rank less that
. So by the induction hypothesis
is homeomorphic to a countable ordinal
for some
where
denotes the first infinite ordinal. Next, notice that
and
are homeomorphic spaces.
Corollary 2.7 ([5]) Any countable scattered Boolean algebra
is isomorphic to
, for some countable ordinal
.
By Theorem 2.6,
is homeomorphic to a countable ordinal, say
.
Theorem 2.8 (FTVI1)
If a non constant real function
is continuous on an interval
of the real line
except on an order-scattered set
, then the interior of
is not empty.
The proof of the theorem follows from next two claims.
Claim 2.9 Let
be the set of real numbers with its usual interval topology. Any order-scattered chain in
is at most countable.
Assume the contrary. By Hausdorff’s theorem on order-scattered chains that is to say, an uncountable scattered chain embeds a sub-chain ordered-isomorphic to the first uncountable ordinal
, see [6], [Theorem 5.28, pp. 87]. Hence,
has an uncountable set of rational numbers, which is a contradiction.
Claim 2.10 Let
be an order-scattered set as in the main theorem. Denote by
the set of all initial chains of
endowed with Tykonov’s topology inherited from
. Then, since
is order-scattered,
is a scattered Boolean algebra i.e.,
is a topologically scattered space. Moreover, since
is order-scattered and countable, it follows that
is isomorphic to an interval algebra over a countable ordinal.
It follows from Theorems 2.5 and 2.6, that
and
are isomorphic Boolean algebras for some
.
By, Claim 2.10,
, as a scattered topological space, has an isolated point (since it is homeomorphic to
), say
. Pick
so that
. So,
. Next,
is continuous on
and thus,
is an interval2: which, in turn, shows that
.
As a consequence, we get the usual TVI-theorem on the real line.
Corollary 2.11 (TVI) If
is a continuous non constant real function on a closed interval
, then
. Therefore, the interior of
is not empty.
Concluding remark 2.12 Let
be a function defined on an interval
. Should the set of discontinuities be scattered, whenever the interior of
is a non empty set, seems a very natural statement. For, recall Darboux theorem for TVI with respect to the derivative of a function: The derivative of a function always satisfies TVI regardless if this derivative is continuous function or not. So, one may ask: How big
, would be for the derivative of a function
? Actually, there is a characterization of the discontinuity set of a derivative and it is found in the following two references: Benedetto [7] (Chapter 1.3.2, Proposition, 1.10, p. 30); and Bruckner [8] (Chapter 3, Section 2, Theorem 2.1, p. 34).
On the other hand, there is a well-known function called the Conway’s base-13 function engineered by J. H. Conway as a counterexample to the converse of the intermediate value theorem. In other words, base-13 function is a function that satisfies the intermediate-value property on any interval but it is discontinuous at every point; since it is unbounded on every interval. Hence, this function answers the first question in this remark.
Finally, the choice of Boolean algebras, in this note, was naturally motivated by the notion of scattered chains in the real line.
Acknowledgements
The author thanks H. Si Kaddour for his suggestions and fruitful comments during the preparation of this note. Moreover, the author dedicates this note to Sami Bekkali.
NOTES
1†, Fez-TVI (FTVI).
2Indeed, let
; assume, e.g.,
. Now, construct two sequences
, so that:
,
and diameter of
converges to zero. So,
. By continuity of
,
. Thus,
is an interval.