T. W. SMYTHE
be able to recognize what is given to me through inner percep-
tion as mine. The problem in Hume’s words is that “self or
person is not any one impression, but that to which our several
perceptions and ideas are supposed to have a reference” (Hume,
251).
Kant believed that this single something, to which all mental
contents are referred, must be found outside of sense experience.
Our awareness of it can no longer be explained within the
model of perceptual awareness itself. In the final analysis, Kant
rejects inner perception as an adequate account of the self and
self-awareness, but he still accepts the framework for marking
off the limits of self-knowledge.
At this point I shall argue that no account of the nature of the
self and self-awareness can be given, independently of the
Kantian system, in terms of what is empirically accessible ex-
clusively to the subject of experience. Although the history of
such attempts has been a long one, I would like to suggest that
the Kantian thesis of the transcendental ego and the ultimacy of
the forms of time and space in which the presentations of iden-
tifiable objects are unified, provides good reasons why this
cannot be done. I shall present these reasons in terms of (1)
awareness of any single object of experience, and (2) awareness
of the spatial or temporal relations between objects of experi-
ence.
Consider the statement “I see a tree.” This statement is true
just in case there is a tree there, and I am looking at it, paying
attention, and so on. I cannot come to realize that it is I who am
seeing the tree, because I can never discover that there is a tree
in my visual field and that I am not perceiving it. The tree can-
not be given in my experience at all unless it is given as my
perception. I cannot perceive the tree, and perceive myself, and
see that it is I who am in the relation of perceiving with the tree.
For, if I could do that, then it would have to be possible for me
to perceive myself, and the tree, and see as a fact about myself,
that I am not perceiving the tree. Clearly this is not possible
because the relation of perceiving or acquaintance, as Kant saw,
is not an empirical, contingent relation. For the self and the
object of experience are co-determinative; each is a necessary
condition for the existence of the other. Thus it is self-contra-
dictory to suppose that I could perceive a tree, and realize, as a
fact about this perceptual relation, that it is not me perceiving
the tree. But this should be possible if we are to account for
self-awareness solely in terms of what is exclusively empiri-
cally ac ce ssible to myself.
Although this line of thought has been used by Shoemaker, I
think it is a variation on the Kantian theme expressed by saying
that the “I think” must be able to accompany all of my repre-
sentations, and cannot itself be accompanied by any further
representation (Kant, 1933: p. B132). In Kant the very distinc-
tion between inner and outer perception presupposes the dis-
tinction between the unity of consciousness and the object of
knowledge. The perception of something as external to myself,
as not me, logically implies an awareness of myself, even if
only in a purely negative sense. And the awareness of some-
thing as inside me, or part of myself, implies there is something
outside, and not in me, from which the current object of
knowledge (my mental state) is to be distinguished. But this
logical polarity between what is perceived as outside and what
is perceived as inside myself, is paralleled by, and made possi-
ble by, the more basic polarity between the unity of conscious-
ness and the object of knowledge. The difference between inner
and outer, internal and external, what is part of me, and what is
not me, presupposes a knowing self or subject which can be
conscious of this difference. And whether an object of percep-
tion be external of my inner goings on, it is never open to ques-
tion whether this is an object of knowledge for myself or
someone else. Part of what it is for the unity of consciousness
to be transcendental, basic, original, and unchangeable is that
its relation to an object of experience is necessary, and can
never itself be empirically given. In addition, it means that our
intellectual self-awareness is immediately given, and not the
result of reflection or introspection.
Consider the statement “S is aware that something A is re-
lated to something B.” where this relation is either spatial or
temporal. This statement is clearly not equivalent to “S knows
something A and something B.” or to the statement “The exis-
tence of A is related to the existence of B.” According to the
first statement, it is the fact of being related that is known, and
this is left out by the other statements. The awareness involves
awareness of a relation and of the fact that A and B are the
relata.
Some traditional ways of putting what is applied in the above
statement is that as awareness of a relation (e.g., succession) is
not the same as a relation of awarenesses (succession of
awarenesses). If A occurred by itself, ceased, and then B oc-
curred, there would not be an awareness of A being related to B.
For there to be this relation, there must be a conscious aware-
ness of A, B, and the relation between them. A conscious
awareness implies not only that objects are so ordered, but a
subject which is not itself located within the ordered relata. In
the case of temporal relations, if S knows that B is followed by
A, S himself cannot be said to precede or follow either of them.
The same considerations apply to space, mental states, proper-
ties of an object, and whatever else can be known relationally.
The above argument is another way of interpreting what is
involved in the assertion that the “I think” must be able to ac-
company all of my representations. A radical empiricist might
counter this argument with the following principle: Given a set
of many elements each related to a special one, we can do away
with the one to which all other elements are created by speak-
ing simply of the set connected by certain relationships among
them. Such an empiricist then owes us an explanation of how
any given element, or subset, can be consciously aware of the
order and arrangements among many of the elements of the set,
including itself, without supposing that the members of the set
are persons. The difficulty of giving a coherent picture along
these lines testifies to the Kantian insight of the ultimacy of the
“I think”. For the “I think” cannot be related to the elements of
experience the way they are related to each other, and cannot be
derived from anything more basic.
Transcendental Self-Awareness
If these two reasons militate against an account of self-
awareness and the self in terms of what is empirically accessi-
ble exclusively to the subject of experiences, then Kant was
correct on insisting on a nonsensuous awareness of the self. Our
awareness of the unity of the self is an awareness of “that unity
of consciousness which precedes all data of intuition, and by
relation to which representation of objects is alone possible”
(Kant, 1933: p. A107). A coherent account of the self in these
terms would show that the I as a thinking subject is the same as
the me, or the awareness I have of myself, independently of the
self-knowledge gained through inner sense. That this approach
Open Access 533