1. Introduction
Let us consider a data model which lives time where the event of interest is a failure (or death) due to the
event,
and the non-zero integer m, the number of possible causes. By convention,
corresponds to the state of functioning (or of life) of the observed individual. It is assumed that the observation is stopped when a failure (or death) occurs, but this observation may be right-censored in a non-informative way. Some examples of this situation corresponds to the case where the event of interest is due to another cause, or withdrawal of the individual from the study or at the end of the study. In the case of right censoring time, the time of failure of year for individuals and their causes are not known to the experimenter. A data model as described above is commonly called “competing risks model” (or competitors) and is studied in fields such as medical control, demography, actuarial science, economics or industrial reliability. In Andersen et al. [4] , an illustration and details of mathematics techniques on competing risks in biomedical applications are developed. For example in the study of AIDS, the different competitive risks can be 1) death due to AIDS, 2) death due to tuberculosis or 3) death due to other causes and in this case
(see Figure 1).
It is important to note that in most data models in competing risks, the functions that characterize the probability distribution of the variable of interest and the marginal are not always observable (see Tsiatis [5] , Heckman and Honoré [6] ). Issues to be resolved include virtually the underlying functions for different causes and effects of covariates on the rate of occurrence of competing risks. One of the problems we may face is that the information on the cause of failure of the individual observation can only be known after the autopsy, while we don’t know anything about individuals censored in monitoring. In addition, the incident distributions (due to specific causes) do not allow to describe satisfactorily the probabilities of the various marginal (failures
case
) in competing risks models. Assumptions of independence of competing risks can help ensure observability in some cases, but they are not reasonable only in such models.
1.1. Related Works
The estimators of Nelson-Aalen and Kaplan-Meier [3] are generally studied in the literature following two approaches: firstly, the method of martingale (Aalen [1] [2] ; Andersen et al. [4] ; Fleming and Harrington [7] , Prentice et al. [8] ) and secondly the law of the iterated logarithm (Breslow and Crowley [9] , Földes and Rejtö [10] or Major and Rejtö [11] , Földes and Rejtö [12] , Gill [13] , Csörgö and Horváth [14] , Ying [15] and Chen and Lo [16] ). Recently, applications have been made in the context of competing risks (Latouche [17] ; Belot [18] ). Latouche [17] states that during the planification of clinical trials, the evaluation of the number of patients to be included is a critical issue because such a formulation does not exist in the Fine and Gray’s [19] model. For this purpose, he therefore computes the number of patients within the context of competition for an inference based function on cumulative incidence and then, he studies the properties of the model of Fine and Gray when it is wrongly specified. Belot [18] presents the data got from randomized clinical tests on prostate cancer patients who died for several reasons.
1.2. Contributions
In this paper, the stochastic processes developed by Aalen [1] [2] are adapted to Nelson-Aalen and KaplanMeier estimators [3] in a context of competing risks (e.g. Aalen and Johansen [20] , Andersen et al. [4] ). We focus only on the complete probability distributions of downtime individuals whose causes are known and which bring us to consider a partition of individuals sub-groups for each cause. We provide a new proof of the consistency of the Nelson-Aalen estimator in the context of competing risks by using the method of martingale. Under the regularity assumptions for the sequence
(
is a sequence of integers such that
and
is the number of observable samples) we obtain an almost-safe speed estimator of Kaplan-Meier [3] which is the same as that obtained by Giné and Guillou [21] which is 
The rest of the paper is organized as follows: Section 2 describes preliminary results and notations used in the paper and Section 3 evaluates the conditional functions of distribution to the specific causes. Section 4 contains the main results of the paper as well as some properties of our estimators obtained. The last section concludes the paper.
2. Preliminary Results
Lifetime analysis (also referred to as survival analysis) is the area of statistics that focuses on analyzing the time

Figure 1. Example of 3 risks competing model.
duration between a given starting point and a specific event. This endpoint is often called failure and the corresponding length of time is called the failure time or survival time or lifetime.
Formally, a failure time is a nonnegative random variable (r.v.)
that describes the length of time from a time origin until an event of interest occurs. We will suppose throughout that 
The most basic quantities used to summarize and describe the time elapsed from a starting point until the occurrence of an event of interest are the distribution function and the hazard function. The cumulative distribution function at time
also called lifetime distribution or the failure distribution, is the probability that the failure time of an individual is less or equal than the value
It is given for
by: 
The function
is right-continuous, nondecreasing and satisfies
and
We denote by
the left-continuous function obtained from
in the following way:

The distribution of
may equivalently be dealt with in terms of the survival function which is given, for
by:

The cumulative hazard function is defined for
by:

When
is continuous, the relation
is valid for all
We can then call
the log-survival function.
If
admits a derivative with respect to Lebesgue measure on
the probability density function exists and is defined for
by:

Heuristically, the function
may be seen as the instantaneous probability of experiencing the event.
With the same hypothesis of differentiability, the hazard function exists and is defined for
by:

The quantity
can be interpreted as the instantaneous probability that an individual dies at time
conditionally on he or she having survived until that time.
For an extensive introduction to lifetime analysis, the reader is referred e.g. to the books of Cox and Oakes [22] and Kalbfleisch and Prentice [23] .
The main difficulty in the analysis of lifetime data lies in the fact that the actual failure times of some individuals may not be observed. An observation is right-censored if it is known to be greater than a certain value, provided the exact time is unknown. Let
be the nonnegative r.v. with distribution function
that stands for the censoring time of the individual. As before, the nonnegative r.v.
with distribution function
denotes the failure time of the individual. If
is censored, instead of
we observe
which gives the information that
is greater than
In any case, the observable r.v. consists of
, where
denotes the indicator function. The nonnegative r.v.
stands for the observed duration of time which may correspond either to the event of interest
or to a censoring time 
As a sequel to above, it is assumed that
and
are independent. Consequently, the random variable
has the distribution function
given by

The following subdistribution functions of
will be needed:

and

The relation

is valid for any 
The relations that connect the subdistribution functions
and to the distribution functions
and
are given by:

and

The cumulative hazard function of
can be expressed as:

Kaplan and Meier [3] introduced the product-limit estimator for the survival distribution function. The estimator of the cumulative hazard function is the Nelson-Aalen estimator introduced by Nelson [24] [25] and generalized by Aalen [1] [2] .
Let
for
be
independent copies of the random vector
Let
be the order statistics associated to the sample
If there are ties between a failure time (or several failure times) and a censoring time, then the failure time(s) is (are) ranked ahead of the censoring time(s).
We define the empirical counterparts of
and
by:



The Kaplan-Meier product-limit estimator is defined for
by:

The Nelson-Aalen estimator for
is then defined for
by:

The following relations are valid for 



where
the Kaplan-Meier estimator of
, is defined for
by:

Let
be a sequence of integers between
and
In order to always have asymptotical results, we suppose that the sequence
satisfies the following hypothesis:
for
large enough, the sequence
is non-increasing and 
for
large enough, the sequence
is non-increasing and there exists a constant
such that
with
is a non-increasing sequence such that:


Condition
is required when applying the results of Gin? and Guillou [21] while Condition
is required when applying the results of Cs
rgö [26] .
The following result formulates the laws of the iterated logarithm-type (LIL-type) result on the mentioned increasing intervals.
Theorem 1 (Csörgö [26] ; Giné and Guillou [21] ) Let
be a sequence of integers such that
and, for the almost sure results, satisfying
We have1:

If, in addition,
is assumed continuous, then we also have:

Proof. See Csörgö [26] ; Giné and Guillou [21] . 
The continuity of
is required to linearize the Kaplan-Meier process. Indeed, if
is continuous, then
can be approximated by
on the random interval
Precisely, we have the following result.
Proposition 1 (Giné and Guillou [21] ) Let
be a sequence of integers satisfying
and Hypothesis
. If
is continuous, then

Proof. See Giné and Guillou [21] . 
3. Evaluation of the Conditional Functions of Distribution to the Specific Causes
Let
be a continuous random variables representing respectively the lifetimes in each of the
risks competing,
be the set of index cause, where 0 corresponds to the condition of the individual observed,
the random variable of the event of interest and
the random variable case, where
if
for all
is the distribution function of 
the survival function such that
the random variable C of the event censoring right,
and for technical reasons,
such that
if (
and
) and
if
.
We notice that
and
are observable and
is so only for
uncensored.
We assume that censorship is not informative. The joint law
is completely specified by the specific incident distributions cause
defined by
(1)
which are none other than the sub-distributions of the specific cause of failure 
The cumulative hazard rate of specific-cause
corresponding to
is given by
(2)
Let
be n-sample of observable triplet
where
and
, with
and where
represent the time that an individual
is subject to the cause
If
and
are independent, the random variable
admits distribution function
defined by
Then the Nelson-Aalen estimator of
is given for
by (see e.g. in Andersen et al. [4] )
(3)
with

and where
(4)
is the counting of the number of failures observed in case of
the time interval
and
(5)
is the number of individuals in the sample observation that survive beyond time
Thus, for any 
(6)
represents the number of individuals who may fall down specific cause
or be censored.
Estimator similar
analogue to (2) and on the sub-group
individuals crashing case
is given by
(7)
and with
and

The relation between the cumulative hazard rate
and survival
in the subgroup Aj is given by2
(8)
A nonparametric estimator of the distribution function
of time life in subgroups
is defined by
(9)
is given by
(10)
The size
of the subgroup
individuals is not observable due to the inaccessibility of all subgroups of specific causes
Nevertheless, we can assign a probability
to each of the individuals belonging to one of the
subgroups. Thus, one can estimate the size
by
given by ( see e.g. in Satten and Datta [27] or Datta and Satten [28] )
where
is the estimator of the probability that the individual n˚
in the sample subgroup
, subset of risk of specific-cause
. Thus, the final estimators for the cumulative hazard rate
due to the specific cause
and the corresponding distribution function
have the respective expressions
(11)
and for 
(12)
4. Main Results
Let
be a positive random variable and
be a censoring variable such that
and
In this model of random censorship, for a sample
subject to a specific causes
we can observe the couple
where
and
with
and where
is the time that an individual
is subject to the cause 
For a given
and an individual
with
the counting process is defined by:

Therefore, if an individual
undergoes event before time
then
otherwise
We can also define the counting process

Naturally, it appears that we considered the information provided over time as a filter, which is used to describe the fact that past information is contained in the current information, hence we have the natural filtration
where

For
and for
we have

If
denotes the left boundary at
of
we have

since, the quantity
takes only the values 0 and 1.
For a given
we define the function

which indicates whether the individual
is still at risk just before time
(the individual has not yet undergone the event). Therefore• if
then,
and
• if
then,

where
is the natural filtration (all information available at time
), where the notation
refers to formal writing of the stochastic integral

writing made possible because
is a growing process. The expression of
in function of the counting process
is given by

Thus, we have 
The stochastic process defined for
and
by

is the martingale associated with the subject at risk
Thereafter
is the compensating process
because it is the integral of the product of two predictable processes.
Theorem 2 Let
be an absolutely continuous lifetime and
be a censoring variable for any arbitrary distribution
Let
be the risk function associated with
Let’s put
and
.
For
the process defined by

is a
martingale if and only if

for
such that 
Proof. See Breuils ([30] , p. 25) and Fleming and Harrington ([7] , p. 26). 
For a given
and a given
, the expressions of
,
and
are those of formulas (4), (5) and (2) respectively. Using these notations, we can directly obtain the following preliminary result:
Proposition 2 For a given
and a given
, the stochastic processes defined by
(13)
is the martingale associated with the subject specific cause 
Proof.

The martingale
represents the difference between the number of failures due to a specific cause
observed in the time interval
, i.e.
, and the number of failures predicted by the model for the
cause. This definition fulfills the Doob-Meyer decomposition.
The first result of this paper concerns the consistency of the Nelson-Aalen estimator for the competing risks based on martingale approach.
Theorem 3 For
such that
we have

Proof.

where the expectation of the martingale
(specific for
cause) is equal to zero and where
Indeed,

Hence, we arrive at result.
Using the fact that

we have:

It follows that
is an asymptotically unbiased estimator of
Hence, we arrived at result. 
Our second LIL-type result provides almost sure and in probability rates of convergence of
to
for
uniformly over the random increasing intervals
. (See is Deheuvels and Einmahl [31] [32] for very fine results of the model law iterated logarithm functional and available in a point or on a compact strictly included in the support of H). This result is consistent with that of Stute [33] which constitutes a compromise between the results of Breslow and Crowley [9] , Földes and Rejtö [10] or Major and Rejtö [11] , and those of Földes and Rejtö [12] , Gill [13] , Csörgö and Horváth [14] , Ying [15] and Chen and Lo [16] .
Following Giné and Guillou [34] , we say that a non-increasing sequence
of numbers is regular if there exists a constant
such that for all
We denote by
the following hypothesis:
for
large enough, the sequence
is regular non-increasing and there exists a constant
such that
with
is a non-increasing sequence such that


Theorem 4 Let
be a sequence of integers such that
for all
and which satisfies hypothesis
for the almost-sure part. For all
we assume that
is alway continuous. Therefore,

where
is the Landau in almost sure sense, and

where
is the Landau in probability.
Both results of Theorem above always provides a rate in probability of uniform convergence of
to
for all
through a random growing intervals 
To prove Theorem 4, we have drawn from results based on the inference of empirical processes, given that in order to linearize the Kaplan-Meier process, it is necessary to impose continuity condition on
Firstly, under the Hypothesis
we have the following result:
Lemma 1 Let
be a sequence of integers such that
and, for the almost-sure results, such that
is satisfied. The rate of convergence of
to
is given by

Proof. The proof of this result follows straightforwardly from the proof of the first part of Theorem 1 concerning the supremum of

Proof of Theorem 4. The following decomposition is obtained for
by means of integration by parts:
(14)
Equality (14) entails that:

Notice that the assumption of continuity of
for
ensures that
is continuous according to proposition 1. We then conclude with Theorem 1 and Lemma 1. 
5. Conclusion
In this paper, we have adapted the stochastic processes of Aalen [1] [2] to the Nelson-Aalen and Kaplan-Meier [3] estimators in a context of competing risks. We have focused particularly on the probability distributions of complete downtime individuals whose causes are known and which bring us to consider a partition of individuals into sub-groups for each cause. We have also provided some asymptotic properties of nonparametric estimators obtained.
Acknowledgements
I would like to thank Prof. Nicolas Gabriel ANDJIGA, Prof. Celestin NEMBUA CHAMENI, Prof. Eugene Kouassi for their support and their advices. I would also like to thank specially Prof. Kossi Essona GNEYOU for his collaboration and his cooperation during the preparation of this paper.
NOTES
1
is the Landau in almost sure sense and
is the Landau in probability.

2
denote the product integral (see Gill & Johansen ).