Natural Rights, Morality, and the Law
Drum Peter
.
DOI: 10.4236/blr.2011.21004   PDF    HTML     9,293 Downloads   16,250 Views   Citations

Abstract

It is argued that despite attempts to discount the importance of natural rights for morality, they are fundamental to it; therefore, so too are natural rights to the legitimacy of the law.

Share and Cite:

D. Peter, "Natural Rights, Morality, and the Law," Beijing Law Review, Vol. 2 No. 1, 2011, pp. 25-31. doi: 10.4236/blr.2011.21004.

Conflicts of Interest

The authors declare no conflicts of interest.

References

[1] St. T. Aquinas, Summa Theologica, 1a2ae. Vol. 18, p. 5, quoting Dionysius.
[2] Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, I, p. 7.
[3] Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, IV, V, p. 1.
[4] Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, V, p. 9.
[5] Aristotle, Rhetoric, I, p. 13.
[6] C. Kluckhohn, “Ethical Relativity, Sic et Non,” The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 52, No. 23, 1955, p. 672.
[7] Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, V, p. 1, quoting Plato, Republic, p. 343c.
[8] In: Joannis Evangelium, Vol. 29, as quoted by St T. Aquinas, Summa Theologica, 1a. Vol. 38, 1 ad 1.
[9] In Joannis Evangelium 29; as quoted by St Thomas Aquinas, Summa Theologica, 1a. 38, 1 ad 1.
[10] This is strangely overlooked by John Kilcullen in his “Medieval and Modern Concepts of Rights: How Do They Differ?”, so that he ends up arguing that natural rights should be recognized just because they are “useful”. Acta Philosophica Fennica, Vol. 87, 2010, pp. 31-62.
[11] Aristotle, Rhetoric, II, p. 2.
[12] J. Bowring ed., “Anarchical Fallacies,” Works, Vol. 2, 1843.
[13] Sophocles, “The Theban Plays,” Harmondsworth, Penguin, 1967, p. 128.
[14] “After Virtue,” Duckworth, London, 1985, p. 69.
[15] “After Virtue,” Duckworth, London, 1985.
[16] “After Virtue,” Duckworth, London, 1985.
[17] Aristotle, Rhetoric, II, p. 9 (emphasis added).
[18] “The Parable of the Fox and the Unliberated Animals,” Ethics, Vol. 88, No. 2, January 1978, p. 122.
[19] P. Singer, “Practical Ethics,” Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1995, p. 19.
[20] P. Singer, “Practical Ethics,” Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1995.
[21] P. Singer, “Practical Ethics,” Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1995, p. 18.
[22] P. Singer, “Practical Ethics,” Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1995, p. 17.
[23] P. Singer, “Practical Ethics,” Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1995, p. 12.
[24] P. Singer, “Practical Ethics,” Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1995, p. 19.
[25] P. Singer, “Practical Ethics,” Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1995, p. 22.
[26] G. E. M. Anscombe, “Modern Moral Philosophy”, Ethics Religion and Politics, Oxford, Blackwell, 1981, p. 40.
[27] A. Dongan, “The Theory of Morality,” Chicago, Chicago University Press, 1977, p. 183.
[28] B. Williams, “Morality - An Introduction to Ethics,” Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1990, p. 109.
[29] R. G. Frey, “Rights, Killing and Suffering,” Blackwell, Oxford, 1983, p. 67.
[30] R. G. Frey, “Rights, Killing and Suffering,” Blackwell, Oxford, 1983, p. 81.
[31] R. G. Frey, “Rights, Killing and Suffering,” Blackwell, Oxford, 1983, p. 51.
[32] R. G. Frey, “Rights, Killing and Suffering,” Blackwell, Oxford, 1983, p. 48.
[33] R. Gaita, “Good and Evil:An Absolute Conception,” MacMillan, London, 1991, p. 4.
[34] R. Gaita, “Good and Evil:An Absolute Conception,” MacMillan, London, 1991.
[35] R. Gaita, “Good and Evil:An Absolute Conception,” MacMillan, London, p. 5.
[36] Gorgias, p. 469b.
[37] “Human Personality” as quoted in R. Gaita, “Good and Evil:An Absolute Conception,” MacMillan, London, p. 7.
[38] J. Feinberg, “Freedom and Fulfilment,” Princeton University Press, USA, 1992, p. 239.
[39] “Human Personality”; as quoted in R. Gaita “Good and Evil:An Absolute Conception,” MacMillan, London.
[40] Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, III, p. 1.
[41] J. J. Thomson, “The Right and the Good”, The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 94, No. 6, June 1997, p. 276,
[42] Aristotle, Politics, VII, p. 3.
[43] Aristotle, Politics, VII.
[44] M. Stocker, “Plural and Conflicting Values,” OUP, Oxford, 1992, p. 9.
[45] R. Gaita, “Good and Evil: An Absolute Conception,” MacMillan, London, 1991, p. 69.
[46] R. Gaita, “Good and Evil: An Absolute Conception,” MacMillan, London, 1991, p. 224.
[47] J. P. Sarte, “Existentialism is a Humanism,” In: W. Kaufmann, ed., Existentialism from Dostoevsky to Sartre, New American Library, New York, 1975.
[48] Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, III, p. 1.
[49] Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, III, p. 58.
[50] Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, II, p. 6.
[51] Aristotle, Rhetoric, I, p. 13.
[52] Aristotle, Politics, VII, p. 16.
[53] I. L. Quincy, “Living a Christian Life,” Franciscan Press, Illinois, 1993, pp. 406-407.
[54] Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, III, p. 1.
[55] Aristotle, Politics, VII, p. 2.
[56] Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, X, p. 9. (Surely “most” is exaggerated, “many” more accurate.)
[57] Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, X.
[58] Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics, V, p. 1.
[59] Sacred Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith, Declaration on Procured Abortion, 18 November, 1974, FN. P. 19.
[60] St T. Aquinas, Summa Theologica, 2a2ae. Vol. 64, p. 1.

Copyright © 2024 by authors and Scientific Research Publishing Inc.

Creative Commons License

This work and the related PDF file are licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License.