Psychology as an Associational Science: A Methodological Viewpoint

Abstract

Unlike the sciences (physics), psychology has not developed in any of its areas (such as perception, learning, cognition) a top-theory like Newtonian theory, the theory of relativity, or quantum theory in physics. This difference is explained by a methodological discrepancy between the sciences and psychology, which centers on the measurement procedure: in psychology, measurement units similar to those in physics have not been discovered. Based on the arguments supporting this claim, a methodological distinction is made between the sciences and psychology as an associational science. It is suggested that that these two kinds of science generate two different classes of technologies. The possibility that in psychology there is a connection between the issue of measurement and the unsolved consciousness/brain problem is discussed.

Share and Cite:

Rakover, S. (2012). Psychology as an Associational Science: A Methodological Viewpoint. Open Journal of Philosophy, 2, 143-152. doi: 10.4236/ojpp.2012.22023.

Conflicts of Interest

The authors declare no conflicts of interest.

References

[1] Baird, J. C., & Noma, E. (1978). Fundamentals of scaling and psycho-physics. New York: John Wiley.
[2] Bayne, T. (2009). Consciousness. In J. Symons, & P. Calvo (Eds.), The Rutledge companion to philosophy of psychology. London: Routledge.
[3] Chalmers, D. (1996). The conscious mind: In search of a fundamental theory. New York: Oxford University Press.
[4] Coombs, C. H., Dawes, R. M., & Tversky, A. (1970). Mathematical psychology: An elementary introduction. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.
[5] Cooper, R. (2004). Why Hacking is wrong about human kinds. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 55, 73-85. doi:10.1093/bjps/55.1.73
[6] Cooper, R., & Shallice, T. (1995). SOAR and the ease for unified theories of cognition. Cognition, 55, 115-149. doi:10.1016/0010-0277(94)00644-Z
[7] Cosmelli, D., Lachaux, J.-P. & Thompson, E. (2007). Neurodynamical appoaches to consciousness. In P. Zelazo, M. Moscovitch, & E. Thompson (Eds.), The Cambridge handbook of consciousness. Cambridge & New York: Cambridge University Press.
[8] De Houwer, J., Fiedler, K., & Moors, A. (2011). Strengths and limitations of theoretical explanations in psychology: Introduction to the special section. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 6, 161-162. doi:10.1177/1745691611400242
[9] Diener, E. (2010). Neuroimaging: Voodoo, new phrenology, or scientific breakthrough? Introduction to special section on fMRI. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 5, 714-715. doi:10.1177/1745691610388773
[10] Garcia-Marques, L., & Ferreira, M. B. (2011). Friends and foes of theory construction in psychological science: Vague dichotomies, unified theories of cognition, and the new experimentalism. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 6, 192-201. doi:10.1177/1745691611400239
[11] Gescheider, G. A. (1997). Psychophysics: The fundamentals. Nahwah: LEA.
[12] Gribbin, J. (2004). The scientists: A history of science told through the lives of its greatest inventors. New York: Random House.
[13] Gross, R. (2009). Themes, issues and debates in psychology (3rd ed.). Abingdon: Hodder
[14] Hacking, I. (1995). The looping effects of human kinds. In D. Sperber, D. Premack, & A. J. Premack (Eds.), Causal cognition: A multi-disciplinary debate. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
[15] Hand, D. J. (2004). Measurement theory and practice: The world through quantification. London: Arnold.
[16] Hilgard, E. R., & Bower, G. H. (1966). Theories of learning (3rd ed.). New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.
[17] Kim, J. (1996). Philosophy of mind. Boulder, CO: Westview Press.
[18] Kimble, G. A. (1961). Higard and Marquis’ conditioning and learning (2nd ed.). New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.
[19] Kouider, S. (2009). Neurobiological theories of consciousness. In W. Banks (Ed.), Encyclopedia of consciousness. Oxford: Elsevier Press. doi:10.1016/B978-012373873-8.00055-4
[20] Kriegel, U. (2007). Philosophical theories of consciousness: Contemporary western perspectives. In P. Zelazo, M. Moscovitch, & E. Thompson (Eds.), The Cambridge handbook of consciousness. Cambridge & New York: Cambridge University Press.
[21] Leahey, T. H. (1992). The mythical revolution of American psychology. American Psychologist, 47, 308-318. doi:10.1037/0003-066X.47.2.308
[22] Leahey, T. H. (2004). A history of psychology (6th ed.). Upper Saddle River, NJ: Pearson/Prentice-Hall.
[23] Levine, J. (1983). Materialism and qualia: The explanatory gap. Pacific Philosophical Quarterly, 64, 354-361.
[24] Lewin, K. (1936). Principles of topological psychology. New York: McGraw-Hill. doi:10.1037/10019-000
[25] Lewis, R. L. (2001). Cognitive theory, SOAR. In N. J. Smelser, & P. B. Baltez (Eds.), International encyclopedia of the social and behavioral sciences. Amsterdam: Pergamon. doi:10.1016/B0-08-043076-7/01583-7
[26] Ludwig, K. (2003). The mind-body problem: An overview. In S. P. Stich, & T. A. Warfield (Eds.), The Blackwell guide to philosophy of mind (pp. 1-46). Malden, MA: Blackwell.
[27] Marx, M. H., & Cronan-Hillix, W. A. (1987). Systems and theories in psychology (4th ed.). New York: McGraw-Hill Book Company.
[28] McCauley, R. N. (2007). Reduction: Models of cross-scientific relations and their implications for the psychology-neuroscience interface. In P. Thagard (ED.), Philosophy of psychology and cognitive science. Amsterdam: Elsevier. doi:10.1016/B978-044451540-7/50021-9
[29] McCauley, R. N., & Bechtel, W. (2001). Explanatory pluralism and heuristic identity theory. Theory & Psychology, 11, 736-760. doi:10.1177/0959354301116002
[30] Macmillan, N. A., & Creelman, C. D. (2005). Detection theory: A user’s guide (2nd ed.). New York: Psychological Press.
[31] Meiser, T. (2011). Much pain, little gain? Paradigm-specific models and methods in Experimental psychology. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 6, 183-191. doi:10.1177/1745691611400241
[32] Michell, J. (1999). Measurement in psychology: Critical history of a methodological concept. Hillsdale, NJ: LEA. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511490040
[33] Miller, G. A. (2010). Mistreating psychology in the decades of the brain. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 5, 716-743. doi:10.1177/1745691610388774
[34] Neisser, U. (1967). Cognitive psychology. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.
[35] Newell, A. (1973). You can’t play 20 questions with nature and win. In W. G. Chase (Ed.), Visual information processing. San Diego, CA: Academic Press.
[36] Newell, A. (1992). SOAR as a unified theory of cognition: Issues and explanations. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 15, 464-492. doi:10.1017/S0140525X00069740
[37] Pachella, R. G. (1974). The interpretation of reaction time in information-processing research. In B. H. Kantowitz (Ed.), Human information processing: Tutorials in performance and cognition. New Jersey: LEA.
[38] Palmer, S. E. & Kimchi, R. (1986). The information processing approach to cognition. In T. J. Knapp & L. C. Robertson (Eds.), Approaches to cognition: Contrasts and controversies. Nahwah: LEA
[39] Polger, T. (2004). Natural minds. Cambridge: MIT press.
[40] Rakover, S. S. (1975). Tolerance of pain as a measure of fear. Learning and Motivation, 6, 43-61. doi:10.1016/0023-9690(75)90034-X
[41] Rakover, S. S. (1980). Role of intertribal interval following escape or avoidance response in bar-press avoidance. Learning and Motivation, 11, 220-237. doi:10.1016/0023-9690(80)90014-4
[42] Rakover, S. S. (1990). Metapsychology: Missing links in behavior, mind and science. New York: Paragon/Solomon.
[43] Rakover, S. S. (1997). Can psychology provide a coherent account of human behavior? A proposed multiexplanation-model theory. Behavior and Philosophy, 25, 43-76.
[44] Rakover, S. S. (2002a). Featural vs. configurational information in faces: A conceptual and empirical analysis. The British Journal of Psychology, 93, 1-30. doi:10.1348/000712602162427
[45] Rakover, S. S. (2002b). Scientific rules of the game and the mind/body: A critique based on the theory of measurement. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 9, 52-58.
[46] Rakover, S. S. (2007). To understand a cat: Methodology and philosophy. Amsterdam/Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
[47] Richards, G. (2010). Putting psychology in its place: A critical historical overview (3rd ed.). London: Routledge.
[48] Rowlands, M. (2009). The mind-body problem. In W. Banks (Ed.), Encyclopedia of Consciousness. Oxford: Elsevier Press. doi:10.1016/B978-012373873-8.00053-0
[49] Schwartz, B. (1989). Psychology of learning and behavior. New York: Norton.
[50] Shimamura, A. P. (2010). Bridging psychological and biological science: The good, and ugly. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 5, 772-775. doi:10.1177/1745691610388781
[51] Stevens, S. S. (1975). Psychophysics: Introduction to its perceptual neural and social prospects. New York: John Wiley.
[52] Sternberg, R. J. (2009). Cognitive psychology (5th ed.). Belmont, CA: Wadsworth.
[53] Suppe, F. (1977). The structure of scientific theories (2nd ed.). Chicago, IL: University of Illinois Press.
[54] Suppe, F. (1979). Theory structure. In P. D. Asquith, & H. E. Kijburg Jr. (Ed.), Current research in philosophy of science. Michigan: Philosophy of Science Association.
[55] Uttal, W. R. (2008). Time, space, and number in Physics and Psychology. Cornwall-on-Hudson, NY: Sloan Publishing.
[56] Watson, J. B. (1913). Psychology as the behaviorist views it. Psychological Review, 20, 158-177. doi:10.1037/h0074428

Copyright © 2024 by authors and Scientific Research Publishing Inc.

Creative Commons License

This work and the related PDF file are licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License.