The Sociology of Knowledge, Citizenship and the Purification of Politics

Abstract

We reinterpret citizenship using Mannheim’s classical sociology of knowledge and through a more recent variant on them in Latour’s argument that “we have never been modern” (Latour, 1991). On that basis, we understand citizenship as a recursive effect of disputes over belonging and membership (Isin, 2002), where those disputes entail the three forms of political rationality or “thought styles” which Mannheim and Latour variously suggested: the linearly individual rationality of liberalism; dialectically collective socialism; and culturally collective conservatism. Marshall defines citizenship as a “status bestowed on those who are full members of a community” (Marshall, 1973). He presents an image of evolutionary progress, from civil to political rights and finally to the social form, in Britain. We argue that Marshall was entangled in evolutionary and teleological images of citizenship. We reinterpret citizenship using Mannheim’s classical sociology of knowledge. We suggest that sociologies of knowledge allow a re-reading of “citizenship” that can accommodate conceptual difficulties. Mannheim called into question the “progress” implied or stated in theories of “stages”. He stressed instead the continuing interaction between different ways of knowing social reality, or between what he called “thought styles”. We apply Mannheim to “citizenship” in order to lift two “purifications”, so that humanity is both natural and political.

Share and Cite:

Donoghue, J. & White, B. (2013). The Sociology of Knowledge, Citizenship and the Purification of Politics. Sociology Mind, 3, 16-18. doi: 10.4236/sm.2013.31003.

Conflicts of Interest

The authors declare no conflicts of interest.

References

[1] Aristotle (1962). The politics. In T. A. Sinclair, & T. J. Saunders (Eds.), Translators. London: Penguin.
[2] Donoghue, J., & White, R. D. (2003). Contested citizenship TASA conference. Armidale: University of New England.
[3] Isin, E. (2002). Being political: Genealogies of citizenship. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.
[4] Kettler, D., & Volker, M. (1995) Karl Mannheim and the crisis of liberalism: The secret of these new times. New Brunswick: Transaction Press.
[5] Latour, B. (1991). We have never been modern catherine porter. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
[6] Mannheim, K. (1922). Structures of thinking. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
[7] Mannheim, K. (1925). The problem of a sociology of knowledge. In K. Wolff (Ed.), From Karl Mannheim (pp. 59-115). New York: Oxford University Press.
[8] Mannheim, K. (1927). Conservative thought. In K. Wolff (Ed.), From Karl Mannheim (pp. 132-222). New York: Oxford University Press.
[9] Mannheim, K. (1929). Ideology and Utopia: An introduction to the sociology of knowledge louis wirth and edward shills. San Diego: Harvest.
[10] Marshall, T. H. (1973). Class,citizenship and social development. Westport, CT: Greenwood.
[11] Marshall, T. H. (1981). Value-problems of welfare capitalism. In The right to welfare and other essays (pp. 104-122). New York: Free Press.
[12] Pels, D. (1996). Karl mannheim and the sociology of scientific knowledge: Toward a new agenda. Sociological Theory, 14, 30-48. doi:10.2307/202151
[13] Shapin, S., & Simon, S. (1985). Leviathan and the air-pump: Hobbes, boyle, and the experimental life. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
[14] Turner, B. S. (1997). Citizenship studies: A general theory. Citizenship Studies, 1, 5-18. doi:10.1080/13621029708420644
[15] White, R. (2000). The life of class: A case study in a sociological concept. Journal of Sociology, 36, 223-238. doi:10.1177/144078330003600206

Copyright © 2024 by authors and Scientific Research Publishing Inc.

Creative Commons License

This work and the related PDF file are licensed under a Creative Commons Attribution 4.0 International License.